PDF
Geometry as made rigorous by Euclid and Descartes
Seminar at Mimar Sinan
David Pierce

Abstract
For Immanuel Kant (born 1724), the discovery of mathematical proof by Thales of Miletus (born around 624 B.C.E) is a revolution in human thought. Modern textbooks of analytic geometry often seem to represent a return to prerevolutionary times. The counterrevolution is attributed to René Descartes (born 1596). But Descartes understands ancient Greek geometry and adds to it. He makes algebra rigorous by interpreting its operations geometrically.
The definition of the real numbers by Richard Dedekind (born 1831) makes a rigorous converse possible. David Hilbert (born 1862) spells it out:
geometry can be interpreted in the ordered field of real numbers, and even in certain countable ordered fields.
In modern textbooks, these ideas are often entangled, making the notion of proof practically meaningless. I propose to disentangle the ideas by means of Book I of Euclid's Elements and Descartes's Geometry.

Introduction
Rigor in mathematics is ability to stand up under questioning. Rigor in education has an extra component: teaching what questions should be asked. This talk is inspired or rather provoked by two books of analytic geometry that fail to be rigorous. One is an old bookAlfred L. Nelson, Karl W. Folley, and William M. Borgman. Analytic
Geometry
. The Ronald Press Company, New York, 1949.
used by my mother in college. When young I used this book in order to sketch the graphs of conic sections and of trigonometric and logarithmic functions. But this book is not a book that one can sit and read for pleasure. I think Spivak's Calculus is such a book. But the analytic geometry book begins with uninspiring exercises about coordinates, with no motivation. Possible motivation can be found in the problem of duplicating the cube, as solved by Menaechmus. The problem is to find two mean proportionals to a unit length and its double. In modern symbolic terms, this is to solve the system\begin{equation*}\frac1x=\frac xy=\frac y2.\end{equation*}From this system we obtain\begin{equation*}\frac1{x^3}=\frac12.\end{equation*}Geometrically then, $x$ is the side of a cube that has twice the volume of the unit cube. Many solutions of this problem are reported by Eutocius (flourished around 500 C.E.) in his commentary on ArchimedesArchimedes. The two books On the sphere and the cylinder, volume I of The works of Archimedes. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2004. Translated into English, together with Eutocius' commentaries, with commentary, and critical edition of the diagrams, by Reviel Netz.. This commentary has been revised by Isidore of Miletus, who, with Anthemius of Tralles, is one of the master-builders of the Ayasofya. Menaechmus was a student of Eudoxus of Knidos and a contemporary of Plato (Heath-ApolloniusApollonius of Perga: Treatise on Conic Sections. University Press, Cambridge, UK, 1896. Edited by T. L. Heath in modern notation, with introductions including an essay on the earlier history of the subject.). Eudoxus invented the theory of proportion found in Euclid's Elements; we shall talk about this later.
Menaechmus's solutionin fact one of his two solutions to the problem above can be understood as follows.
We obtain two equations\begin{align*}xy&=2,& 2x&=y^2.\end{align*}It is known that these are the equations of certain conic sections, which Apollonius would later call the hyperbola and the parabola. The point is that Menaechmus knows that the curves really can be obtained by slicing a cone. The hyperbola can be given asymptotes.
[pspicture]\begin{pspicture}(-0.5,-0.5)(4.3,3) \psline(0,3)(0,0)(4,0) \psline(0,2)(1,2)(1,0) \psplot{0.67}{4}{2 x div} \psplot{0}{2.25}{4 x mul sqrt} \uput[80](1,2){$\Theta$} \uput[l](0,2){K} \uput[d](0,0){$\Delta$} \uput[d](1,0){Z} \uput[d](4,0){H} \end{pspicture}[/pspicture]
Figure 1: Menaechmus’s finding of two mean proportionals

Then the axis of the parabola will be the horizontal asymptote of the hyperbola. The coordinates of the intersection of the two conic sections solve the original problem.
Was Menaechmus doing analytic geometry as we understand it? Perhaps not. Today we would just calculate the solution to the original system as\begin{equation*}(x,y)=(\sqrt[3]2,\sqrt[3]4).\end{equation*}But a point with these coordinates cannot be found with the usual tools of straightedge and compass. Menaechmus gives us reason to believe that this point exists anyway. The reason he gives is geometric.
Two thousand years later, René Descartes seems to share the view that solutions to equations should be understood geometrically. For example, in figure below,
[pspicture]\begin{pspicture}(-5,-2)(-1,2.5)
\psline(-4.5,-2)(-4.5,2.5)
\psline(-3.5,-2)(-3.5,2.5)
\psline(-2.5,-2)(-2.5,2.5)
\psline(-1.5,-2)(-1.5,2.5)
\psline(-5,-1)(-1,-1)
\rput(-2.3,-1.3){$A$}
\rput(-2.3,0.5){$B$}
\pscircle(-3.232,0.268){0.05}
\rput(-3.2,0.5){$C$}
\rput(-3.7,0.5){$D$}
\rput(-3.7,-1.3){$E$}
\rput(-4.7,0.5){$F$}
\rput(-4.7,-1.3){$G$}
\rput(-1.3,0.5){$H$}
\rput(-1.3,-1.3){$I$}
\rput(-3.2,-1.3){$M$}
\rput(-3.08,-0.37){$x$}
\rput(-2.87,0.12){$y$}
\psline[linestyle=dashed](-4.5,0.268)(-1.5,0.268)
\psline[linestyle=dashed](-3.232,-1)(-3.232,0.268)
\end{pspicture}[/pspicture]
Figure 2: Descartes’s locus problem

assuming $GE=EA=AI=a$, suppose we want the locus of points $C$ such that\begin{equation*}CF\cdot CD\cdot CH=CB\cdot CM\cdot AI,
\end{equation*}that is,\begin{equation*}(2a-y)(a-y)(a+y)=yxa.\end{equation*}Given any value of $y$, we can compute $x$ and thus sketch the curve as in figure below.
[pspicture]\psset{unit=5mm}
\begin{pspicture}*(-5,-2)(3,7)
\psline(-4,-2)(-4,7)
\psline(-2,-2)(-2,7)
\psline(0,-2)(0,7)
\psline(2,-2)(2,7)
\psline(-5,0)(3,0)
\psset{linestyle=dashed}
\psplot{-5}{-0.1}{x 4 add x x mul 4 sub mul 2 div x div}
\psplot{0.1}{3}{x 4 add x x mul 4 sub mul 2 div x div}
\end{pspicture}[/pspicture]
Figure 3: The locus itself

But Descartes finds it worthwhile to do more. He shows that the point $C$ lies on the intersection, shown in figure below,
[pspicture]\psset{unit=5mm}
\begin{pspicture}*(-5,-2)(3,7)
\psline(-4,-2)(-4,7)
\psline(-2,-2)(-2,7)
\psline(0,-2)(0,7)
\psline(2,-2)(2,7)
\psline(-5,0)(3,0)
\psset{linestyle=dashed}
\psplot{-5}{3}{x x mul 4 div 2 add}
\psplot{-4}{0}{x 4 add}
\uput[dr](0,2){$K$}
\uput[ur](0,4){$L$}
\uput[dl](-4,0){$G$}
\end{pspicture}[/pspicture]
Figure 4: Descartes’s geometrical solution

    • a parabola with axis $AB$ and latus rectum $a$ whose vertex $K$ slides along $AB$,
    • the straight line through $GL$, where $KL=a$.
Thus the curve given by the cubic equation above becomes geometrically meaningful.

Again, we think the problem of duplicating the cube is solved simply by taking the cube root of $2$.
But how is this taken? There is an algorithm for finding decimal approximations.
But why do we think these approximations have a limit? We can just declare that $\sqrt[3]2$ is some infinite decimal expansion.
But why do we think that infinite decimal expansions like this compose a field?

Richard Dedekind claims that, before he gave a rigorous definition of the rational numbers, the theorem\begin{equation*}\sqrt2\cdot\sqrt3=\sqrt6\end{equation*}had not been proved. David Fowler (author of The Mathematics of Plato’s Academy [8]) seems to be correct that Dedekind is correct.

There is no algorithm for computing with infinite decimals. For example, what is the following sum?\begin{equation*}
3.1415926535\dots+0.8584073464\dots
\end{equation*}It is either $3.9\dots$ or $4.0\dots$, but we cannot specify a number of digits that are sufficient to tell us which. For example\begin{equation*}
1.222\dots\times0.818181\dots\end{equation*}which is\begin{gather*}\left(1+\frac29\right)\times\frac{81}{99}=\frac{11}9\times\frac{81}{99}=1;\end{gather*}but no amount of multiplying finite decimal approximations tells us that the product is not required to begin as $0.9$.
Dedekind's definition of the real numbers explicitly avoids making use of geometric notions. Therefore we can use the set of ordered pairs of real numbers as a model for geometric axioms, thus showing that these axioms are consistent. David Hilbert does this. Conversely, the Euclidean plane can be used to turn a straight line into a model of axioms for an ordered field. Descartes suggests this. David Hilbert fills in the missing details. More recently, Robin HartshorneGeometry: Euclid and beyond. Undergraduate Texts in Mathematics. Springer-Verlag, New York, 2000. does the same, using theorems about circles from Book III of Euclid's Elements. In fact Book I of the Elements is enough.

Thus there are two complementary approaches to analytic geometry. Either geometry or algebra can be taken as fundamental. But textbooks assume both of these foundations. I think this is a defect of rigor.